哈佛大學(xué)公開課程公正該如何做是好英文文本全集_第1頁
哈佛大學(xué)公開課程公正該如何做是好英文文本全集_第2頁
哈佛大學(xué)公開課程公正該如何做是好英文文本全集_第3頁
哈佛大學(xué)公開課程公正該如何做是好英文文本全集_第4頁
哈佛大學(xué)公開課程公正該如何做是好英文文本全集_第5頁
已閱讀5頁,還剩81頁未讀, 繼續(xù)免費閱讀

下載本文檔

版權(quán)說明:本文檔由用戶提供并上傳,收益歸屬內(nèi)容提供方,若內(nèi)容存在侵權(quán),請進(jìn)行舉報或認(rèn)領(lǐng)

文檔簡介

1、哈佛大學(xué)公開課程公正:該如何做是好?justice: what's the right thing to do? this is a course about justice and we begin with a story.suppose you're the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the track at 60 miles an hour.and at the end of the track you notice five workers working on the

2、 track.you try to stop but you can't, your brakes don't work.you feel desperate because you know that if you crash into these five workers, they will all die.let's assume you know that for sure.and so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at

3、 the end of that track, there is one worker working on the track.your steering wheel works, so you can turn the trolley car, if you want to, onto the side track killing the one but sparing the five.here's our first question: what's the right thing to do?what would you do? let's take a po

4、ll.how many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? raise your hands.how many wouldn't? how many would go straight ahead?keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead.a handful of people would, the vast majority would turn.let's hear first, now we need to begin to inves

5、tigate the reasons why you think it's the right thing to do.let's begin with those in the majority who would turn to go onto the side track. why would you do it?what would be your reason? who's willing to volunteer a reason?go ahead. stand up.because it can't be right to kill five pe

6、ople when you can only kill one person instead.it wouldn't be right to kill five if you could kill one person instead.that's a good reason.that's a good reason. who else?does everybody agree with that reason? go ahead.well i was thinking it's the same reason on 9/11 with regard to th

7、e people who flew the plane into the pennsylvania field as heroes because they chose to kill the people on the plane and not kill more people in big buildings.so the principle there was the same on 9/11.it's a tragic circumstance but better to kill one so that five can live, is that the reason m

8、ost of you had, those of you who would turn? yes?let's hear now from those in the minority, those who wouldn't turn. yes.well, i think that's the same type of mentality that justifies genocide and totalitarianism.in order to save one type of race, you wipe out the other.so what would you

9、 do in this case?you would, to avoid the horrors of genocide, you would crash into the five and kill them?presumably, yes.you would? -yeah.okay. who else? that's a brave answer.thank you.let's consider another trolley car case and see whether those of you in the majority want to adhere to th

10、e principle "better that one should die so that five should live."this time you're not the driver of the trolley car, you're an onlooker. you're standing on a bridge overlooking a trolley car track.and down the track comes a trolley car, at the end of the track are five workers

11、, the brakes don't work, the trolley car is about to careen into the five and kill them.and now, you're not the driver, you really feel helpless until you notice standing next to you, leaning over the bridge is a very fat man.and you could give him a shove.he would fall over the bridge onto

12、the track right in the way of the trolley car. he would die but he would spare the five.now, how many would push the fat man over the bridge?raise your hand. how many wouldn't? most people wouldn't. here's the obvious question.what became of the principle "better to save five lives

13、even if it means sacrificing one?"what became of the principle that almost everyone endorsed in the first case?i need to hear from someone who was in the majority in both cases.how do you explain the difference between the two? yes.the second one, i guess, involves an active choice of pushing a

14、 person down which i guess that person himself would otherwise not have been involved in the situation at all.and so to choose on his behalf, i guess, to involve him in something that he otherwise would have escaped is, i guess, more than what you have in the first case where the three parties, the

15、driver and the two sets of workers, are already, i guess, in the situation.but the guy working, the one on the track off to the side, he didn't choose to sacrifice his life any more than the fat man did, did he?that's true, but he was on the tracks and.this guy was on the bridge.go ahead, yo

16、u can come back if you want. all right.it's a hard question. you did well. you did very well.it's a hard question.who else can find a way of reconciling the reaction of the majority in these two cases? yes.well, i guess in the first case where you have the one worker and the five, it's a

17、 choice between those two and you have to make a certain choice and people are going to die because of the trolley car, not necessarily because of your direct actions.the trolley car is a runaway thing and you're making a split second choice.whereas pushing the fat man over is an actual act of m

18、urder on your part.you have control over that whereas you may not have control over the trolley car.so i think it's a slightly different situation.all right, who has a reply?that's good. who has a way?who wants to reply?is that a way out of this?i don't think that's a very good reaso

19、n because you choose toeither way you have to choose who dies because you either choose to turn and kill the person, which is an act of conscious thought to turn, or you choose to push the fat man over which is also an active, conscious action.so either way, you're making a choice.do you want to

20、 reply?i'm not really sure that that's the case.it just still seems kind of different.the act of actually pushing someone over onto the tracks and killing him, you are actually killing him yourself.you're pushing him with your own hands.you're pushing him and that's different tha

21、n steering something that is going to cause death into another.you know, it doesn't really sound right saying it now.no, no. it's good. it's good.what's your name?andrew.andrew.let me ask you this question, andrew.yes.suppose standing on the bridge next to the fat man, i didn't h

22、ave to push him, suppose he was standing over a trap door that i could open by turning a steering wheel like that.would you turn?for some reason, that still just seems more wrong.right?i mean, maybe if you accidentally like leaned into the steering wheel or something like that.but. or say that the c

23、ar is hurtling towards a switch that will drop the trap.then i could agree with that.that's all right. fair enough.it still seems wrong in a way that it doesn't seem wrong in the first case to turn, you say.and in another way, i mean, in the first situation you're involved directly with

24、the situation.in the second one, you're an onlooker as well.all right. -so you have the choice of becoming involved or not by pushing the fat man.all right. let's forget for the moment about this case.that's good.let's imagine a different case.this time you're a doctor in an emer

25、gency room and six patients come to you.they've been in a terrible trolley car wreck.five of them sustain moderate injuries, one is severely injured, you could spend all day caring for the one severely injured victim but in that time, the five would die.or you could look after the five, restore

26、them to health but during that time, the one severely injured person would die.how many would save the five?now as the doctor, how many would save the one?very few people, just a handful of people.same reason, i assume.one life versus five?now consider another doctor case.this time, you're a tra

27、nsplant surgeon and you have five patients, each in desperate need of an organ transplant in order to survive.one needs a heart, one a lung, one a kidney, one a liver, and the fifth a pancreas.and you have no organ donors.you are about to see them die.and then it occurs to you that in the next room

28、there's a healthy guy who came in for a check-up.and he's - you like that - and he's taking a nap, you could go in very quietly, yank out the five organs, that person would die, but you could save the five.how many would do it?anyone? how many?put your hands up if you would do it.anyone

29、in the balcony?i would.you would? be careful, don't lean over too much.how many wouldn't?all right. what do you say?speak up in the balcony, you who would yank out the organs. why?i'd actually like to explore a slightly alternate possibility of just taking the one of the five who needs a

30、n organ who dies first and using their four healthy organs to save the other four.that's a pretty good idea.that's a great idea except for the fact that you just wrecked the philosophical point.let's step back from these stories and these arguments to notice a couple of things about the

31、way the arguments have begun to unfold.certain moral principles have already begun to emerge from the discussions we've had.and let's consider what those moral principles look like.the first moral principle that emerged in the discussion said the right thing to do, the moral thing to do depe

32、nds on the consequences that will result from your action.at the end of the day, better that five should live even if one must die.that's an example of consequentialist moral reasoning.consequentialist moral reasoning locates morality in the consequences of an act, in the state of the world that

33、 will result from the thing you do.but then we went a little further, we considered those other cases and people weren't so sure about consequentialist moral reasoning.when people hesitated to push the fat man over the bridge or to yank out the organs of the innocent patient, people gestured tow

34、ard reasons having to do with the intrinsic quality of the act itself, consequences be what they may.people were reluctant.people thought it was just wrong, categorically wrong, to kill a person, an innocent person, even for the sake of saving five lives.at least people thought that in the second ve

35、rsion of each story we considered.so this points to a second categorical way of thinking about moral reasoning.categorical moral reasoning locates morality in certain absolute moral requirements, certain categorical duties and rights, regardless of the consequences.we're going to explore in the

36、days and weeks to come the contrast between consequentialist and categorical moral principles.the most influential example of consequential moral reasoning is utilitarianism, a doctrine invented by jeremy bentham, english political philosopher.the most important philosopher of categorical moral reas

37、oning german philosopher immanuel kant.so we will look at those two different modes of moral reasoning, assess them, and also consider others.if you look at the syllabus, you'll notice that we read a number of great and famous books, books by aristotle, john locke, immanuel kant, john stewart mi

38、ll, and others.you'll notice too from the syllabus that we don't only read these books; we also take up contemporary, political, and legal controversies that raise philosophical questions.we will debate equality and inequality, affirmative action, free speech versus hate speech, same sex mar

39、riage, military conscription, a range of practical questions. why?not just to enliven these abstract and distant books but to make clear, to bring out what's at stake in our everyday lives, including our political lives, for philosophy.and so we will read these books and we will debate these iss

40、ues, and we'll see how each informs and illuminates the other.this may sound appealing enough, but here i have to issue a warning.and the warning is this, to read these books in this way as an exercise in self knowledge, to read them in this way carries certain risks, risks that are both persona

41、l and political, risks that every student of political philosophy has known.these risks spring from the fact that philosophy teaches us and unsettles us by confronting us with what we already know.there's an irony.the difficulty of this course consists in the fact that it teaches what you alread

42、y know.it works by taking what we know from familiar unquestioned settings and making it strange.that's how those examples worked, the hypotheticals with which we began, with their mix of playfulness and sobriety.it's also how these philosophical books work. philosophy estranges us from the

43、familiar, not by supplying new information but by inviting and provoking a new way of seeing but, and here's the risk, once the familiar turns strange, it's never quite the same again.self knowledge is like lost innocence, however unsettling you find it; it can never be un-thought or un-know

44、n.what makes this enterprise difficult but also riveting is that moral and political philosophy is a story and you don't know where the story will lead.but what you do know is that the story is about you.those are the personal risks.now what of the political risks?one way of introducing a course

45、 like this would be to promise you that by reading these books and debating these issues, you will become a better, more responsible citizen; you will examine the presuppositions of public policy, you will hone your political judgment, you will become a more effective participant in public affairs.b

46、ut this would be a partial and misleading promise.political philosophy, for the most part, hasn't worked that way.you have to allow for the possibility that political philosophy may make you a worse citizen rather than a better one or at least a worse citizen before it makes you a better one, an

47、d that's because philosophy is a distancing, even debilitating, activity. and you see this, going back to socrates, there's a dialogue, the gorgias, in which one of socrates' friends, callicles, tries to talk him out of philosophizing.callicles tells socrates "philosophy is a pretty

48、 toy if one indulges in it with moderation at the right time of life. but if one pursues it further than one should, it is absolute ruin.""take my advice," callicles says, "abandon argument. learn the accomplishments of active life, take for your models not those people who spend

49、 their time on these petty quibbles but those who have a good livelihood and reputation and many other blessings."so callicles is really saying to socrates "quit philosophizing, get real, go to business school." and callicles did have a point.he had a point because philosophy distance

50、s us from conventions, from established assumptions, and from settled beliefs.those are the risks, personal and political.and in the face of these risks, there is a characteristic evasion.the name of the evasion is skepticism, it's the idea - well, it goes something like this - we didn't res

51、olve once and for all either the cases or the principles we were arguing when we began and if aristotle and locke and kant and mill haven't solved these questions after all of these years, who are we to think that we, here in sanders theatre, over the course of a semester, can resolve them?and s

52、o, maybe it's just a matter of each person having his or her own principles and there's nothing more to be said about it, no way of reasoning.that's the evasion, the evasion of skepticism, to which i would offer the following reply.it's true, these questions have been debated for a v

53、ery long time but the very fact that they have recurred and persisted may suggest that though they're impossible in one sense, they're unavoidable in another.and the reason they're unavoidable, the reason they're inescapable is that we live some answer to these questions every day. s

54、o skepticism, just throwing up your hands and giving up on moral reflection is no solution.immanuel kant described very well the problem with skepticism when he wrote "skepticism is a resting place for human reason, where it can reflect upon its dogmatic wanderings, but it is no dwelling place

55、for permanent settlement.""simply to acquiesce in skepticism," kant wrote, "can never suffice to overcome the restlessness of reason."i've tried to suggest through these stories and these arguments some sense of the risks and temptations, of the perils and the possibilit

56、ies.i would simply conclude by saying that the aim of this course is to awaken the restlessness of reason and to see where it might lead.thank you very much.like, in a situation that desperate, you have to do what you have to do to survive.-you have to do what you have to do?you got to do what you g

57、ot to do, pretty much.without any food, you know, someone just has to take the sacrifice.someone has to make the sacrifice and people can survive.alright, that's good.what's your name?marcus.-marcus, what do you say to marcus?last time, we started out last time with some stories, with some m

58、oral dilemmas about trolley cars and about doctors and healthy patients vulnerable to being victims of organ transplantation.we noticed two things about the arguments we had, one had to do with the way we were arguing.we began with our judgments in particular cases.we tried to articulate the reasons

59、 or the principles lying behind our judgments.and then confronted with a new case, we found ourselves reexamining those principles, revising each in the light of the other.and we noticed the built in pressure to try to bring into alignment our judgments about particular cases and the principles we w

60、ould endorse on reflection.we also noticed something about the substance of the arguments that emerged from the discussion.we noticed that sometimes we were tempted to locate the morality of an act in the consequences, in the results, in the state of the world that it brought about.and we called this consequentialist moral reasoning.but we also noticed that in some cases, we weren't swayed on

溫馨提示

  • 1. 本站所有資源如無特殊說明,都需要本地電腦安裝OFFICE2007和PDF閱讀器。圖紙軟件為CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.壓縮文件請下載最新的WinRAR軟件解壓。
  • 2. 本站的文檔不包含任何第三方提供的附件圖紙等,如果需要附件,請聯(lián)系上傳者。文件的所有權(quán)益歸上傳用戶所有。
  • 3. 本站RAR壓縮包中若帶圖紙,網(wǎng)頁內(nèi)容里面會有圖紙預(yù)覽,若沒有圖紙預(yù)覽就沒有圖紙。
  • 4. 未經(jīng)權(quán)益所有人同意不得將文件中的內(nèi)容挪作商業(yè)或盈利用途。
  • 5. 人人文庫網(wǎng)僅提供信息存儲空間,僅對用戶上傳內(nèi)容的表現(xiàn)方式做保護(hù)處理,對用戶上傳分享的文檔內(nèi)容本身不做任何修改或編輯,并不能對任何下載內(nèi)容負(fù)責(zé)。
  • 6. 下載文件中如有侵權(quán)或不適當(dāng)內(nèi)容,請與我們聯(lián)系,我們立即糾正。
  • 7. 本站不保證下載資源的準(zhǔn)確性、安全性和完整性, 同時也不承擔(dān)用戶因使用這些下載資源對自己和他人造成任何形式的傷害或損失。

評論

0/150

提交評論